Connect
MJA
MJA

Professionalism for medicine: opportunities and obligations

Sylvia R Cruess, Sharon Johnston and Richard L Cruess
Med J Aust 2002; 177 (4): 208-211. || doi: 10.5694/j.1326-5377.2002.tb04735.x
Published online: 19 August 2002

Abstract

  • Physicians' dual roles — as healer and professional — are linked by codes of ethics governing behaviour and are empowered by science.

  • Being part of a profession entails a societal contract. The profession is granted a monopoly over the use of a body of knowledge and the privilege of self-regulation and, in return, guarantees society professional competence, integrity and the provision of altruistic service.

  • Societal attitudes to professionalism have changed from supportive to increasingly critical — with physicians being criticised for pursuing their own financial interests, and failing to self-regulate in a way that guarantees competence.

  • Professional values are also threatened by many other factors. The most important are the changes in healthcare delivery in the developed world, with control shifting from the profession to the State and/or the corporate sector.

  • For the ideal of professionalism to survive, physicians must understand it and its role in the social contract. They must meet the obligations necessary to sustain professionalism and ensure that healthcare systems support, rather than subvert, behaviour that is compatible with professionalism's values.

A distinguished journalist has stated that with globalisation has come "a sense that your job, community, or work place can be changed at any moment by anonymous economic and technological forces that are anything but stable".1 Medicine has not escaped this phenomenon. In developed countries it has changed in one or two generations from a cottage industry to one consuming a significant portion of each country's gross domestic product. Solo practice has become rare, new payment methods have appeared, primary care and specialised medicine have become more complex, and public expectations have altered dramatically. In all parts of the developed world physicians have had to adapt to a new and sometimes unfamiliar world work environment. Most have three concerns:

  • their ability to provide quality care;

  • the threats to their clinical autonomy; and

  • the survival of the values to which they committed themselves when they recited the Hippocratic Oath or its modern equivalent.2,3

Among the many responses of the medical profession to the present situation has been an effort to rearticulate and re-emphasise the values that have traditionally characterised medicine.

In society, the physician fills two roles — that of a healer and a professional.4 In the Western world, the healing tradition goes back to Hellenic Greece, and the Hippocratic Oath (or its modern derivative) has long been an important part of the self-image of the physician.5 The professions have their origins in the guilds and universities of medieval Europe and England. During these times physicians served only the élite, until the Industrial Revolution provided sufficient wealth for healthcare to be purchased, and science made it worth purchasing.4-9 The two roles of physicians are linked by codes of ethics governing their behaviour in both roles, and by science which empowers both roles.

What is a profession?

A working definition of "profession" from the Oxford English Dictionary,10 with elements drawn from the literature, is:

The contract between professions and society is relatively simple. The professions are granted a monopoly over the use of a body of knowledge, as well as considerable autonomy, prestige, and financial rewards — on the understanding that they will guarantee competence, provide altruistic service, and conduct their affairs with morality and integrity. In outlining the characteristics of a profession, the obligations which the profession acquires will be linked with each characteristic.

The complexity of the knowledge base

There is general agreement that the raison d'être for professions is the complexity of the specialised knowledge which each profession controls.6-8 In spite of modern information technology, this knowledge is not easily understood by the public, and consequently the professions are given substantial control over its use. In this, they acquire responsibility for its integrity, for its proper application, and for its expansion, which, for medicine, means the support of science. Finally, professions have an obligation to transmit their knowledge by teaching it to future practitioners, the general public, and their patients.

Altruism

There is agreement that the trust placed in the professions12 and their privileged status are only justified by the expectation that they will be altruistic. For physicians this means consistently placing the interests of individual patients and society above their own.7,13,14 Professions must be devoted to the public good.

Autonomy

Another important characteristic of a profession is autonomy. Individually, physicians are granted sufficient autonomy to act in the best interests of their patients.7,8 Until late in the 20th century, autonomy was expressed in a paternalistic fashion, but modern society, recognising patient autonomy, now views the physician–patient relationship as a partnership.15

The profession is also granted collective autonomy through self-regulation.4,6-8 It has the privilege and obligation to set and maintain standards for education and training, entry into practice, and the standards of practice. It must guarantee the competence of its practitioners, and has an absolute obligation to discipline unprofessional, incompetent, or unethical conduct.

Professional associations

Professional associations and licensing bodies are characteristic of all professions.4,7 They operate with State-sanctioned authority, which may be altered if society becomes dissatisfied with their performance. Collegiality helps to establish common goals and encourage compliance with them.16 Their role in self-regulation is major, as is the expectation that they will advise the public as experts in their domain. The associations and licensing bodies have a primary role in guaranteeing the quality of healthcare services.

Medical associations also have an obligation to protect the interests of their individual members. The two roles can conflict and professional associations have not always managed this conflict wisely, being seen to ignore the public's interests in favour of their own.3,17 This has contributed to a loss of trust in all professions, including medicine.12 Because the function of professional associations is so important, they require the support of their members. Individual physicians are responsible for the actions of their associations.

Accountability

For centuries, physicians were accountable to their patients and to their profession.2,7,15,18 The importance of modern healthcare to society's well-being, coupled with its cost, has engendered a new accountability at economic and political levels.19 Thus, physicians continue to be accountable for patient care and self-regulation, while acquiring accountability for the financial impact of their decisions and for the health and the well-being of populations.19,20

Morality and integrity

The professions are expected to be moral, ethical, and carry out their activities with integrity.13,14,18 Indeed, professionalism has been defined as "an ideal to be pursued",18 recognising that physicians will not always meet all of the conditions required, but must continually strive to do so.

Not only are individual physicians expected to demonstrate morality and virtue, but so are the institutions which represent them.21 Thus, professional associations and licensing bodies must not engage in activities which detract from the morality and integrity of the profession. Finally, morality and virtue must be integral to the rules, processes and procedures by which medicine governs and regulates itself.22

Codes of ethics

All professions have developed codes of ethics which govern the behaviour of their members6,8 and represent the applied morality of the profession. They serve as guidelines for the behaviour of their members and as an important part of the public's expectations of the profession.

The evolution of the concept of the professions

The literature on the professions is extensive, but, until recently, was found almost exclusively in the social sciences and philosophy, and thus was difficult for physicians to access. This is unfortunate, because there were times when the literature was highly critical of the medical profession. It both reflected and helped to shape public opinion and public policy, and physicians were unaware of its impact on the perception of the profession. In the past decade, analyses have appeared in publications readily accessible to physicians.4,23-28

From the early 1900s until the 1950s, the literature was supportive of the concept of professionalism.29-34 It described the professions, the rationale for their being, and stressed the service commitment of individual professionals. It recognised the conflict between altruism and self-interest, but believed that commitment to service would result in altruistic behaviour.

In the questioning society of the 1960s,7,8,35-39 the literature changed. It asserted that physicians exploited their monopoly to create a demand for services which they then satisfied.37,39 It identified serious failures in self-regulation,7,35,39 and abuse of collegiality to protect incompetent or unethical physicians. It criticised physicians for pursuing their own financial interests at the expense of both individual patients and society. Finally, it questioned the benefits of professionalism to society.35-37,39

With the growing importance of governments and the corporate sector in healthcare, the literature of the past two decades has shown a significant shift.6,13,18,22 It documents the fact that medicine has lost control over the medical marketplace, no longer dictating its structure, methods of payment, or levels of remuneration.20 Depending on the country, control shifted from the profession to the State and/or the corporate sector. Social scientists recognised that organising healthcare around models based on either State or corporate control imposes different goals and values from models which are structured around professionalism. They have returned to support the "professional model"22 as being more value laden, but remain unanimous that professionalism must be devoted to the public good — one observer calls it "civic professionalism".13

The challenges of the future

The changes in healthcare systems throughout the developed world have been dramatic, resulting in medicine having diminished input into major policy decisions by the State and corporate sector.8,20 The increased complexity and cost of modern medicine undoubtedly made this inevitable, but the consequences for the profession have been substantial. The application of "accounting logic"20 to the practice of medicine has intruded into the autonomy of individual practitioners.6,11,17 As the profession participated in the process of renegotiating its social contract with society, it has been at a disadvantage and has not done so effectively. The negotiations appear to primarily concern methods and amounts of remuneration, as well as patterns of practice, but there is evidence that physicians are as worried about the values of their profession as about financial issues.40 Thus far, values do not seem to have been a distinct issue at the negotiating table.

The principal threats to medicine's professional status come from public mistrust of the profession as a whole. Two major factors contribute to this mistrust — public perception that medicine failed to self-regulate in a way that can guarantee competence, and that it put its own interest above that of patients and the public.13,17,22 The well-publicised Bristol affair,41 and the reports on medical errors in Australia42 and the United States,43 have contributed to the belief that medicine has protected incompetent or unethical colleagues in the name of collegiality. This belief persists in spite of regulatory procedures becoming more rigorous and more open.

Medicine's reputation for altruism was easier to maintain before the advent of national health services. The tradition of caring for those who could not afford medical care was strong. The virtual disappearance of the truly medically indigent patient in most developed countries, and the necessity to negotiate for both levels of remuneration and details of practice, have accentuated this problem. In addition, the dual role of medical associations8,17,44 — acting as expert advisors on matters of health as well as representing their members — has created a difficult conflict of roles. The literature on professionalism is surprisingly kind to the motivation and performance of individual doctors, but is highly critical of the performance of medical associations.6,8,22

Can the ideal represented by professionalism be preserved in a way that will give continued meaning to the practice of medicine? There are reasons for hope.13,17,22,45 As control of healthcare has passed from medicine to the State and the corporate sector, so has the blame for defects in the healthcare system. Patients remain attached to their physicians and do not wish either the State or corporate sector to make decisions about their care. The public and physicians share a view of the changes needed in healthcare systems.6 Thus, there is an opportunity for medicine to rebuild trust.

Opportunities for action

Medicine has several opportunities for action.

  • Because professionalism is at the core of medicine's social contract, physicians must understand the origins and nature of professional status, and the obligations necessary to sustain it. Professionalism must be taught explicitly, and those serving as role models require detailed knowledge of professionalism.4,23 The growing medical literature on how to teach and evaluate professionalism,4,23-28 the initiatives taken by educational and certifying bodies26,46,47 and the important recent elaboration of an "International Charter on Professionalism"48 aid in this venture.

  • Medicine's professional associations must be extremely wise in how they negotiate for their members.17 Any hint that the public good is being ignored during these negotiations can be damaging to the credibility of the profession and result in loss of the trust, which is so essential to the healing process.3

  • The privilege of self-regulation entails an absolute obligation to guarantee the competence of members. The setting and maintenance of standards is of overriding importance, and issues such as recertification and revalidation are, without question, now regarded as professional obligations. The disciplining of unethical or incompetent practitioners must be rigorous, open, and have the support of every practising physician. A heavy price has already been paid for failures in this domain.

  • Individual physicians must consider the consequences of being seen to put self-interest above that of their patient. Altruism and ethical conduct must serve as the backdrop against which medicine is practised.

  • Even if the medical profession itself carries out the above actions, it is unlikely that the values cherished by physicians for centuries can be preserved unless their preservation is encouraged and supported by society through the structure of the healthcare system. Healthcare systems can actively promote desirable behaviour or they can encourage physicians to place their own interest first. If undue competition among physicians is promoted by the system, one should not be surprised if competitive physician-entrepreneurs emerge. If medical manpower policies coupled with payment methods actively encourage physicians to see large numbers of patients to maintain an adequate income, they will do so. Physicians will maintain professional values, but not at any price.49 Thus, the support of policy makers in preserving a value-based healthcare system becomes critical.50 For this to occur, the issue must be considered to be important by those negotiating on behalf of the profession.

In closing, it is worthwhile to quote William Sullivan, a prominent medical sociologist: "Neither economic incentives nor technology nor administrative control has proved an effective surrogate for the commitment to integrity evoked in the ideal of professionalism."13 Without question, the medical profession itself wishes to function within a system dominated by a healthy and flourishing professionalism. As Sullivan22 and Freidson50 point out, there should also be substantial advantages to society in preserving professionalism as an effective value-based system. The original reason for the use of the profession as a means of organising healthcare was because of the complexity of the knowledge base, the difficulty in regulating it, and the presumption that the profession would be altruistic and devoted to the public good. We believe that nothing in the past 150 years has altered that fact. Thus, both society and the profession should wish for the same type of physician — competent, moral, idealistic, and altruistic. This is best guaranteed by a healer functioning as a respected professional.

  • Sylvia R Cruess1
  • Sharon Johnston2
  • Richard L Cruess3

  • Centre for Medical Education, McGill University, Montreal, Quebec, Canada.


Correspondence: rcruess@med.mcgill.ca

Acknowledgements: 

We acknowledge funding from the McConnell Family Foundation, Montreal, QC, Canada.

Competing interests:

None identified

  • 1. Friedman T. The lexus and the olive tree: understanding globalization. New York: Anchor Books, 2000: 12.
  • 2. Dunning AJ. Status of the doctor — present and future. Lancet 1999; 354 Suppl IV: 18.
  • 3. Edwards N, Kornacki MJ, Silversin J. Unhappy doctors: what are the causes and what can be done? BMJ 2002; 324: 835-838.
  • 4. Cruess RL, Cruess SR. Teaching medicine as a profession in the service of healing. Acad Med 1997; 72: 941-952.
  • 5. Sohl P, Bessford R. Codes of medical ethics: traditional foundations and contemporary practice. Soc Sci Med 1980; 22: 1175-1179.
  • 6. Krause E. Death of the guilds: professions, states and the advance of capitalism, 1930 to the present. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1996.
  • 7. Freidson E. Professional dominance: the social structure of medical care. Chicago: Aldine, 1970.
  • 8. Starr P. The social transformation of American medicine. New York: Basic Books, 1984.
  • 9. Willis R. The medical profession in Australia. In: Hafferty FW, McKinlay JB, editors. The changing medical profession: an international perspective. New York: Oxford University Press, 1993: 104-115.
  • 10. Oxford English Dictionary. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989.
  • 11. Ham C, Alberti KG. The medical profession, the public, and the government. BMJ 2002; 324: 838-842.
  • 12. Mechanic D. Changing medical organization and the erosion of trust. Milbank Q 1996; 74: 171-189.
  • 13. Sullivan W. Work and integrity: the crisis and promise of professionalism in North America. New York: Harper Collins, 1995: 16.
  • 14. Perkin H. The rise of professional society: England since 1880. London: Routledge, 1989.
  • 15. Pellegrino ED. Trust and distrust in professional ethics. In: Pellegrino ED, Veatch RM, Langen JP, editors. Ethics, trust, and the professions. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1991: 69-85.
  • 16. Ihara CK. Collegiality as a professional virtue. In: Flores A, editor. Professional ideals. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1988: 56-65.
  • 17. Stevens R. Public roles for the medical profession in the United States: beyond theories of decline and fall. Milbank Q 2001; 79: 327-353.
  • 18. Kultgen JH. Ethics and professionalism. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1988.
  • 19. Emanuel EJ, Emanuel LL. What is accountability in health care? Ann Intern Med 1996; 124: 229-239.
  • 20. Moran M, Wood B. States, regulation and the medical profession. Buckingham: Open University Press, 1993.
  • 21. Pellegrino ED, Relman A. Professional medical associations: ethical and practical guidelines. JAMA 1999; 282: 1954-1956.
  • 22. Freidson E. Professionalism reborn: theory, prophecy and policy. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 1994.
  • 23. Cruess SR, Cruess RL. Professionalism must be taught. BMJ 1997; 315: 1674-1677.
  • 24. Cruess RL, Cruess SR, Johnston SE. Renewing professionalism: an opportunity for medicine. Acad Med 1999; 74: 878-884.
  • 25. Cruess RL, Cruess SR, Johnston SE. Professionalism — an ideal to be pursued. Lancet 2000; 365: 156-159.
  • 26. Irvine D. The performance of doctors: the new professionalism. Lancet 1999; 353: 1174-1177.
  • 27. Wynia MK, Latham SR, Kao AC, et al. Medical professionalism in society. N Engl J Med 1999; 341: 1612-1616.
  • 28. Swick HM. Towards a normative definition of professionalism. Acad Med 2000; 75: 612-616.
  • 29. Webb S, Webb B. Professional associations. New Statesman 1917; 9 (Suppl): 7-19.
  • 30. Tawney RH. The acquisitive society. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1920.
  • 31. Flexner A. Is social work a profession? School and Society 1915; 1(26): 901-911.
  • 32. Brandeis L. Business — a profession. Boston: Hole, Cushman and Flint, 1933.
  • 33. Carr-Saunders AM, Wilson PA. The professions. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1933.
  • 34. Parsons T. The professions and social structure. Social Forces 1939; 17: 457-467.
  • 35. Freidson E. Profession of medicine: a study of the sociology of applied knowledge. New York: Dodd and Mead, 1970.
  • 36. McKinlay J. Towards proletarianization of physicians. In: Derber E, editor. Professionals as workers: mental labor in advanced capitalism. Boston: G K Hall, 1982: 37-62.
  • 37. Larson M. The rise of professionalism: a sociological analysis. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1977.
  • 38. Haug M. Deprofessionalization: an alternate hypothesis for the future. Sociol Rev Monogr 1973; 20: 195-211.
  • 39. Johnson T. Professions and power. London: Macmillan Press, 1972.
  • 40. Blendon RJ, Schoen C, Donelan K, et al. Physicians' views on quality of care — a five-country comparison. Health Aff 2001; 20: 233-243.
  • 41. Smith R. All changed, changed utterly. British medicine will be transformed by the Bristol case. BMJ 1993; 316: 1917-1918.
  • 42. Wilson RM, Runciman WB, Gibberd RW, et al. The quality in Australian Health Care Study. Med J Aust 1995; 163: 458-471. <eMJA pdf>
  • 43. To err is human: building a safer health system. Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 2000.
  • 44. Berwick TN. Medical associations, guilds or leaders. BMJ 1997; 314: 1564-1565.
  • 45. Southon G, Braithwaite J. The end of professionalism? Soc Sci Med 1998; 46: 23-28.
  • 46. American Board of Internal Medicine. Project professionalism. Philadelphia: ABIM, 1995.
  • 47. Association of American Medical Colleges. Professionalism in contemporary medical education: an invitational colloqium. Washington, DC: AAMC, 1998.
  • 48. Medical professionalism in the new millennium: a physicians' charter. Lancet 2002; 359: 520-522 [and Ann Intern Med 2002; 136: 243-246.]
  • 49. Casalino LP. The unintended consequences of measuring quality on the quality of care. N Engl J Med 1999; 341: 1147-1150.
  • 50. Freidson E. Professionalism: the third logic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001.

Author

remove_circle_outline Delete Author
add_circle_outline Add Author

Comment
Do you have any competing interests to declare? *

I/we agree to assign copyright to the Medical Journal of Australia and agree to the Conditions of publication *
I/we agree to the Terms of use of the Medical Journal of Australia *
Email me when people comment on this article

Online responses are no longer available. Please refer to our instructions for authors page for more information.